"The Lachmann Legacy: An Agenda for Macroeconomics"
South African Journal of Economics
vol. 65, no. 4 (December), 1997, pp. 459-481
An Agenda for Macroeconomics
Roger W. Garrison
Adopting a means-ends framework for macroeconomic theorizing is a way
of emphasizing the critical time dimension—the time that elapses between
the employment of means and the achievement of ends. In a modern, decentralized,
capital-intensive economy, the original means and the ultimate ends are
linked by a myriad of decision of intervening entrepreneurs. As the market
process moves forward, each entrepreneur is guided by circumstances created
by the past decisions of all entrepreneurs and by expectations about the
future decisions of consumers and of other entrepreneurs. These are the
decisions that give rise to what Ludwig Lachmann has called an intricate
latticework of capital and what we will call—to emphasize the time dimension—the
intertemporal structure of capital.
Austrian macroeconomics,
then, concerns itself with two critical aspects of economic reality: the
intertemporal capital structure and entrepreneurial expectations. Mainstream
macroeconomics has long ignored the first-mentioned aspect but has become
keenly attentive—almost obsessively attentive—to the second. On my interpretation,
Lachmann's writings argue for a better balance of attention and suggest
that the mainstream's overemphasis of expectations is directly related
to its underemphasis of capital structure.
What About Expectations?
There is some dispute concerning the Austrian school's attention to
expectations as evidenced by conflicting views about the writings of Ludwig
von Mises: "Mises always emphasized the role of expectations" (Phelps,
1970, p. 129); "Mises hardly ever mentions expectations" (Lachmann, 1976,
p. 58). Is it possible that these seemingly opposing pronouncements are
somehow both true? The "always" and even the "hardly ever" (Lachmann didn't
say "never") make us suspect that both involve overstatement. But the validity
of each derives from the different alternative treatments of expectations
to which Misesian economics is being compared. Phelps was providing a contrast
to the 1960s view of the tradeoff between inflation and unemployment. The
idea that this tradeoff is a stable one and that it provides a menu of
social choice for policymakers requires a wholesale neglect of expectations.
Lachmann was providing a contrast to the 1930s view of investment in an
uncertain world. Equilibration, according to the Swedish economists, involves
a playoff between expected and realized values of the level of investment;
persistent disequilibrium, according to Keynes, is attributable to the
absence of any relevant and timely connection between long-term expectations
and underlying economic realities. In comparison to Keynes and even the
Swedes, Mises underemphasized expectations. This was Lachmann's judgment.
In a letter of August 1989,
Lachmann posed to me a direct question about Mises's and Hayek's neglect
of expectation (a neglect he referred to in a subsequent letter as "a simple
matter of historical fact"). "Do you agree with me that in the 1930s Hayek
and Mises made a great mistake in neglecting expectations, in failing to
extend Austrian subjectivism from preferences to expectations?" His particular
phrasing of this question links it directly to his 1976 article, in which
he traced the development of subjectivism "From Mises to Shackle." Also,
Lachmann's question was a leading question, followed immediately with "What,
in your view, are the most urgent tasks Austrians must now address?" Lachmann
himself had spent several decades grappling with expectations. He recognized
in an early article (1943) that expectations in economic theorizing presents
us with a unique challenge. They cannot be regarded as exogenous variables.
We must be able to give some account of "why they are what they are" (p.
65). But neither can expectations be regarded as endogenous variables.
To do so would be to deny their inherent subjectivist quality. This challenge
always emphasized but never actually met by Lachmann has been dubbed the
"Lachmann problem" by Roger Koppl (1998, p. 61.)
My response to Lachmann
did not deal head-on with the Lachmann problem but focused instead on Hayek
and Keynes and derived from considerations of strategy. Hayek was trying
to counterbalance Keynes, whose theory featured expectations but neglected
capital structure. Without an adequate theory of capital, expectations
became the wild card in Keynes's arguments. Guided by his "vision" of economic
reality, a vision that was set in his mind at and early age, he played
this wild card selectively—ignoring expectations when the theory fit his
vision, relying heavily on expectations when he had to make it fit. Hayek's
countering strategy is made clear in his Pure Theory of Capital (pp.
407ff.): "[Our] task has been to bring out the importance of the real factors
[as opposed to the psychological factors], which in contemporary discussion
are increasingly disregarded." But in countering Keynes's "expectations
without capital theory," Hayek produced—or so it could be argued—a "capital
theory without expectations." In response to Lachmann's question about
the most urgent
tasks, I suggested that we need to put capital theory (with expectations)
back into macroeconomics and that my inspiration for working in this direction
was Lachmann's own writings.
What I saw then as inspiration
I see now as legacy. Though exhibiting increasing emphasis on the uncertain
future and decreasing confidence that the market's equilibrium tendencies
will prevail, Lachmann's writings—from his 1943 "Role of Expectations"
article, to his 1956 Capital and Its Structure to his 1986 The
Market as An Economic Process—were focused sharply on both capital
and expectations. During the three decades that separated the two books,
his own thinking grew ever closer to Shackle's. The macroeconomy to him
became the kaleidic society. The existence of equilibrating forces was
not in doubt. But neither was the existence of disequilibrating forces.
And there was no way to know which, in the end, would win out. Among Austrian
economists, Lachmann was virtually along in his agnosticism about the ability
of the market economy to coordinate.
If Lachmann's legacy is
to bear fruit, today's Austrian macroeconomists will have to allow their
thinking to be guided by the question "What about capital"? But as a preliminary
task, they will have to respond effectively to the question that has become
the litmus test for modern macroeconomic theorizing: "What about expectations?"
So: what about expectations
in today's macroeconomics? In earlier decades, this question could be asked
out of concern about emphasis—too little or too much? But more recently
the question is posed impishly—with serious doubts that any theory that
does
not feature so-called rational expectations can survive a candid response.
The question has gotten the attention in recent years of defenders as well
as critics of Austrian theory and particularly of the Austrian theory of
the business cycle. But as we have seen, the challenge itself is not new
to the Austrians. Hayek (1939) dealt early on with "Price Expectations,
Monetary Disturbances, and Malinvestments." Lachmann (1943 and 1945) raised
the issue anew—and with a hint of impishness—arguing that the treatment
(or neglect) of expectations in Mises's account of business cycles constitutes
the Achilles' heel of the Austrian theory. Mises's glib response (1943),
in which he acknowledged an implicit assumption about expectations (their
being fairly elastic), suggested that he did not take Lachmann's critical
assessment to be a particularly hard-hitting one. More recently, however,
critics within the Austrian school (e.g., Butos, 1997) have charged that
modern Austrian macroeconomists ignore expectations or, at least, do not
deal adequately with them.
Modern defenders of the
Austrian theory are often put on the spot to respond to these critics in
a way that (1) recognizes the treatment of expectations as the sine
qua non of business cycle theory it has come to be in modern macroeconomics,
(2) reconciles the Austrian view with the kernel of truth in the rational
expectations theory, and (3) absolves modern expositors of Austrian business
cycle theory for not giving expectations their due. There is no direct
answer, of course, that will satisfy the modern critic who issues the challenge
in the form of the rhetorical question: "What about expectations?"—hence
the impish tone with which it is posed.
While my response to Lachmann
in 1989 focused on the strategic considerations made by Hayek in his battle
with Keynes, my reply to the imps of the 1990s hinges on the fact that
Hayek lost the battle. Reflection reveals that this question, or, more
accurately, the context in which it is asked, is wholly anachronistic.
Modern treatments of expectations, which can be understood only in the
context of the macroeconomics that grew out of the Keynesian revolution,
cannot simply be grafted onto the Austrian theory, whose origins predate
Keynes and whose development entailed an explicit rejection of Keynes's
aggregation scheme. Accordingly, a brief history of macroeconomic thought
is prerequisite to a satisfactory answer to any question about the role
of expectations in the Austrian theory of the business cycle.
The Keynesian Spur
It was in the 1930s that macroeconomics and, with it, business cycle
theory, broke away as a separate subdiscipline. To describe the breakaway,
some writers use terms such as Keynesian detour or Keynesian diversion,
which suggest that the path of development was, for a time, less direct
than it might have been; my Keynesian spur (analogous to a spur line of
a railway) suggests development in the direction of a dead end. As Keynesianism
worked its way through the profession, macroeconomics came to be defined
not as a set of issues concerning the overall performance of the economy
but as a particular way of theorizing about the economy. For purposes of
gauging the economy's ability to employ resources, the new macroeconomics
focused on the aggregate demand for output relative to the economy's potential
output. For purposes of dealing with the issue of stability and charting
the dynamic properties of the economy (such as those implied by the multiplier-accelerator
process), the output of investment goods was separated from the output
of consumption goods: Investment is the unstable component, and consumption
is the stable component of aggregate demand. The summary treatment of inputs
was even more severe. Consistent with the strong labor-market orientation,
inputs were treated as if they consisted exclusively of labor or could
be reckoned in labor-equivalent terms. The structure of capital was assumed
fixed, the extent of its actual utilization changing in virtual lockstep
with changes in the employment of labor. Income earned by workers was reckoned
as the going wage rate times the number of (skill-adjusted) worker hours,
and changes in labor income were taken to imply proportional changes in
total income.
Dropping out of the macroeconomic
picture was any notion that labor income may move against other forms of
income, as the classical economists had emphasized, as well as the notion
that changes in the structure of capital—more of some kinds, less of other
kinds—may figure importantly in the economy's overall performance. These
changes in relative magnitudes, by virtue of their being relative changes,
were no part of the new macroeconomics. In fact, it was the masking of
all the economic forces that assert themselves within the designated
aggregate magnitudes, particularly those that are at work within the investment
aggregate, that allowed macroeconomics to make such a clean break from
the pre-Keynesian modes of thought.
Analytical simplicity was
achieved in part by the aggregation per se and in part by the fact
that the featured input aggregate was labor rather than capital. All the
thorny issues of capital—involving unavoidable ambiguities in defining
it, measuring it, and theorizing about it—were set aside as the simpler
issues of labor became the near-exclusive focus. The preeminence of labor
in this regard seemed almost self-justifying not only on the grounds of
its relative simplicity but also on the grounds that it is our concern
for workers, after all, and their periodically falling victim to economywide
bouts of unemployment that justify our study of macroeconomic phenomena.
Despite its being descriptively accurate, "labor-based macroeconomics"
is a term not in general use today but only because virtually all modern
macroeconomics is labor-based.
A few noncontroversial propositions
about spending on consumption goods as it relates to consumers' incomes
is enough to establish a clear dependence of aggregate demand and hence
aggregate income on investment spending, which—absent capital theory—seems
to be rooted in psychology rather than in economics (Keynes, 1936, p. 161-63).
It follows in short order that an economy dominated by such a dependency
and constricted by an assumed fixity of the wage rate is inherently unstable.
Movements in the investment aggregate, up or down, give rise to magnified
movements—in the same direction—of income and consumption. Classical theory
is reduced to the minimal role of identifying the level of income that
constitutes full employment, implying that changes in the Keynesian aggregates
are real changes for levels below full employment and nominal changes for
levels above.
A comparison of the Keynesian
analytics with those that predate the breakaway of macroeconomics confirm
that what counts in classical theorizing is the interplay among landlords,
workers, capitalists, and entrepreneurs. Relative and sometimes opposing
movements of the incomes associated with these four categories gives the
economy its stability. For Keynes, all such relative movements were downplayed
or ignored. It is as if an automotive engineer, in his quest for analytical
simplicity, modeled a four-wheeled vehicle as a wheelbarrow and then declared
it inherently unstable. To impose stability on the Keynesian wheelbarrow,
some external entity would have to have a firm grip on both handles. Those
handles, of course, took the form of fiscal policy and monetary policy.
The mixed economy, whose market forces are continually countered by policy
activism, could achieve a level of performance that a wholly private macroeconomy
could never be able to achieve on its own. If sufficiently enlightened
about the inherent flaws of capitalism, the fiscal and monetary authorities
could keep the Keynesian wheelbarrow between the hedgeposts of unemployment
and inflation.
Although simple in the extreme,
highly aggregative, labor-based macroeconomics was ripe for development.
Questions about each of the aggregates and their relations to one another
gave rise to virtually endless variations on a theme. What about consumer
behavior? Beyond the simple linear relationship with current income, consumers
may behave in accordance with the relative-income hypothesis (Duesenberry),
the life-cycle hypothesis (Modigliani), or the permanent-income hypothesis
(Friedman). What about the interest elasticity of the demand for money
and of the demand for investment funds? Different assumptions, as might
apply in the short run and the long run, allowed for some reconciliation
between Keynesian and Monetarist views. What about wealth effects? What
about investment lags? What about differential stickiness between wages
and prices?
The "what-about" questions
served to enrich the research agenda of macroeconomics in all directions.
The highly aggregative, labor-based macroeconomics survived them all, even
thrived on them, by providing answers that set the stage for still more
what-about questions. Even the critical question, "What about the real-cash-balance
effect?," whose answer initially separated the Keynesians from the classicists,
ultimately worked in favor of policy activism. The Keynesians embraced
the notion that the economy could settle into an equilibrium characterized
by persisting unemployment. Critics such as Haberler, Pigou, and eventually
Patinkin argued that falling wages and prices would increase the real value
of money holdings and that the spending out of these real cash balances
would restore the economy to full employment. That is, even with all the
other equilibrating forces buried deep in Keynes's macroeconomic aggregates,
there remained a single margin (between money and output) on which to achieve
a full-employment equilibrium. Real cash balances became, in effect, a
balancing act that allowed the market economy to ride the Keynesian wheelbarrow
as if it were a unicycle! Keynesians could concede the theoretical point
while making the classically oriented critics look impractical if not downright
foolish. If the critics willingly accepted Keynes's aggregation scheme,
they would have to accept the policy implication of his theory as well.
Considerations of practicality strongly favor a policy activism that takes
the macroeconomy to be a Keynesian wheelbarrow rather than a policy of
laissez-faire that presumes it to be a classical unicycle.
The one exception to the
agenda-expanding queries was the question that eventually came to be dreaded
by practitioners of the new macroeconomics: What about expectations? In
the face of the Monetarist counterrevolution and particularly the introduction
of the expectations-augmented Phillips curve, it was no longer acceptable
to assume that workers expect stable prices even as their real wage rate
is being continually and dramatically eroded by inflation. The notion of
a stable downward-sloping Phillips curve was no longer possible to maintain.
Allowing workers to adjust their expectations of next year's rate of inflation
on the basis of last year's experience did not much improve the theory's
logical consistency or preserve its policy implications. The short-run
Phillips curve was not exploitable in any welfare-enhancing sense. Even
half-serious attempts to answer the question about expectations led to
a contraction rather than an expansion of the research program. Logically
consistent and rigorous answers led to a virtual implosion. If macroeconomists
could provide simple answers to the what-about questions, why couldn't
market participants? Some entrepreneurs and speculators could literally
figure out the same things that the macroeconomists had figured out. Others
could mimic these macro-savvy market participants, and still others could
catch on if only by stumbling around in an economy where the highest profits
go to those most in the know. Any theory about systematic macroeconomic
relationships and certainly any policy recommendation would have to be
based on the assumption of rational expectations.
Embracing the rational-expectations
theory had the effects of bringing long-run conclusions into the short
run (Maddock and Carter, 1982), denying the possibility of using fiscal
and monetary policy to stimulate or stabilize the economy (Sargent and
Wallace, 1975 and 1976), and—despite the fact that these ideas were an
outgrowth of Monetarism—questioning the importance of money in theorizing
about the macroeconomy (Long and Plosser, 1983). The sequential attempts
to deal with expectations became more and more directed towards preserving
the internal logic of macroeconomics at the expense of maintaining a link
between macroeconomic theory and macroeconomic reality. All too soon, the
very idea of business cycles was purged of any meaning that might connect
this term with actual historical events.
Macroeconomics in the hands
of the new classical economists, who tend to judge all other macroeconomic
theories in terms of their treatment of expectations, lost the flavor but
not the essence of its highly aggregative forerunners. The 1970s witnessed
a search by macroeconomists for their microeconomic moorings. That is,
recognizing that macroeconomics had pulled anchor in the 1930s and had
been adrift for four decades, they sought to reanchor it in the fundamentals.
The actual movement back to the fundamentals, however, affected form more
than substance. The macroeconomic aggregates were replaced by representative
agents. But the illusion of these agents forming expectations, making choices
and otherwise doing their own thing is just that, an illusion. What the
representative agent represents is the aggregate. Further, the things that
the agent is imagined to be doing leave little scope for theorizing at
either a microeconomic or a macroeconomic level. Phelps (1970, p. 5), who
pioneered this search for microfoundations, clearly recognized the nature
of the new classical theorizing: "On the ice-covered terrain of the Walrasian
economy, the question of a connection between aggregate demand and the
employment level is a little treacherous." The terrain is featureless,
and the individuals, a.k.a. agents, are indistinguishable from the
representative agent. (One is reminded of the once-popular poster showing
ten thousand penguins dotting an ice-scape—with an anonymous penguin in
the back ranks belting out the title bar of I Gotta Be Me.) In typical
new classical models, the ice-scape is an especially bleak one, allowing
for the existence of only one commodity. And to rule out such considerations
as decisions about storing the commodity, leasing it, or capitalizing the
value of its services, the single commodity is itself conceived as a service
indistinguishable from the labor that renders it. This construction eliminates
the need to distinguish even between the input and the output. In order
to keep such an economy from degenerating into autarky, with each penguin
rendering the service to himself, we are to think in terms of some particular
service which, due to technological—or anatomical—considerations, one penguin
has to render to another. "Back-scratching services" is offered as the
paradigm case (Barro, 1981, p. 83).
In their zeal to isolate
the issue of expectations and elevate it to the status they believe it
deserves in macroeconomics, the new classical economists have produced
models whose sterility is matched by no other. Theorizing centers on the
question of whether or not a change in the demand for the commodity is
a real change or only a nominal change. The expectation that a change will
prove to be only a nominal one implies that no real supply-side response
is called for; the expectation that a change will prove to be a real one
implies the need for a corresponding reallocation of the representative
penguin's time—between scratching backs and consuming leisure.
In order even to raise the
issue of cyclical variation in output, new classical macroeconomists, whose
models are constructed to deal explicitly and rigorously with expectations,
must contrive some time element between (1) the observation of a change
in demand and (2) the realization of the true nature (nominal or real)
of the change. A construction introduced by Phelps (1970, p. 6.) involves
a multiplicity of islands, each with its own underlying economic realities
but all under the province of a single monetary authority. (Here, we overlook
the fact that the very existence of money on the new classical ice-scape
presents a puzzle in its own right.) In accordance with the fundamental
truth in the quantity theory of money, a monetary expansion has a lasting
influence only on nominal variables. Thus, in Phelps' construction, real
changes are local; nominal changes are global. The representative penguin
on a given island observes instantly each change in demand for the service
but discovers only later (on the basis of information from distant islands)
whether the change is nominal or real. The microeconomics of maximizing
behavior in the face of uncertainty allows us to conclude that even before
discovering the true nature of the change in demand, the representative
penguin will respond to the change as if it were at least partially real.
Monetary manipulation, then, can cause temporary changes in real magnitudes.
This is the model that underlies the new classical monetary misperception
theory of the business cycle.
An alternative development
of new classicism, one that avoids the contrived and theoretically troublesome
notion of monetary misperception, simply denies the existence of business
cycles as conventionally conceived—or as modeled with the aid of the distinction
between local and global information. According to real business cycle
theory, what appear to be cyclical variations in macroeconomic magnitudes
are actually nothing more than market adjustments to randomly occurring
technology shocks to the economy—even if the shocks themselves cannot always
be independently identified. Changes in the money supply have nothing to
do with these adjustments (or are an effect rather than a cause of them).
Further, the adjustments take place at an optimum (profit-maximizing) pace.
Whereas conventional macroeconomics attempts to track the cyclical variation
of the economy's output around its trend-line growth path, real business
cycle theory denies that trend-line growth can be meaningfully defined.
It holds that actual variations in output reflect variations in the economy's
potential. According to this strand of new classicism (and despite its
being labeled real business cycle theory), movements in the macroeconomy's
input and output magnitudes are not actually cyclical in any economically
relevant sense.
Still another alternative
development closely tied to the idea of rational expectation is one that
recognizes the possibility of macroeconomic downturns but denies any role
to misperceptions. The variations in output can be attributed to certain
obstacles (costs) that prevent the instant adjustment of nominal magnitudes.
Technology shocks need not be the only source of change. Changes in the
money supply can affect the economy, too. There are no significant information
lags, but penguins cannot translate changes in demand instantaneously into
the appropriate changes in nominal magnitudes. Prices are sticky. The stickiness,
however, can be explained in terms of optimizing behavior and rational
expectations. So-called menu costs (the costs of actually producing new
menus, catalogs, and price tags) stand in the way of instantaneous price
adjustments. These are the ideas of new Keynesian theory (Ball et al.,
1988)—"Keynesian" because of price stickiness; "new" because the stickiness
is not indicative of irrational behavior. (We will argue in Chapter 11
that new Keynesian ideas in the context of a complex decentralized capital-intensive
economy are worthy of attention.)
In response to the question
"What about expectations?" we get new classical monetary misperception
theory, real business cycle theory, and new Keynesian theory. This is the
state of modern macroeconomics. While each of these theories include rigorous
demonstrations that the assumptions about expectations are consistent with
the theory itself, none are accompanied with persuasive reasons for believing
that there is a connection between the theoretical construct and the actual
performance of the economy over a sequence of booms and busts. Applicability
has been sacrificed to rigor. The Keynesian spur has led us to this dead
end.
Meeting the Challenge to Austrian Theory
The very fact that the Austrian theory of the business cycle is offered
as a theory applicable to many actual episodes of boom and bust—from the
Great Depression to the Bush recession—seems to raise the suspicions of
modern critics. If the theory has maintained its applicability, it obviously
has not suffered the implosion that follows from the attempt to deal adequately—rigorously—with
expectations. The critic imagines that he can stand flat-footed in front
of an Austrian business cycle theorist, ask "What about expectations?"
and then step back to watch the Austrian theory degenerate into some story
about back-scratching penguins. The questioner expects that the Austrian
theorist will first grapple ineffectively for an acceptable answer and
then finally realize the true significance of this implosion-inducing question.
Some modern Austrians (Butos
and Koppl, 1993) have argued that dealing effectively with expectations
may be a matter of doing the right kind of cognitive psychology. They suggest
that Hayek's Sensory Order (1952), which deals with sensory data
in the context of the structure of the human mind, may be relevant here.
In this view, dealing with expectations consists not of choosing among
alternative hypotheses (static, adaptive, rational) but of providing a
theoretical account of the mental process through which expectations are
formed and then integrating this theory with the theory of the business
cycle. It is as if we must begin our story with photons striking the retinas
of the entrepreneurs and end it with the ticker tape reporting the consequent
capital gains and losses. Any actual integration of a theory of expectations
in this sense with the theory of the business cycle would have to begin
with a Crusoe economy and then, after introducing Friday, proceed to a
barter economy, to a market economy, to a market economy with a central
bank, and finally to an episode of credit expansion in this last-mentioned
setting. This exercise may well have some payoffs, although it is difficult
to anticipate even the nature of the possible payoffs. But surely it is
doubtful that such a merging of cognitive psychology and macroeconomics,
if in fact it could be done, would provide answers that would satisfy either
the critics or the defenders of the Austrian theory.
In light of the evolution
of modern macroeconomic thought (from its break with the rest of economics
and particularly with capital theory, to its simplification on the basis
of the now-conventional macroeconomic aggregates, to its blossoming in
the hands of practitioners exploring the many variations on a theme, to
its eventual implosion in the face of embarrassing questions about expectations),
the Austrians are ill-advised to take the question about expectations at
face value. "What about expectations?" proved to be an embarrassing question
for conventional macroeconomists; it need not be an embarrassing one for
Austrian economists, whose theory has not suffered the same evolutionary
fate. Further, the Austrians can hardly be expected to resist embarrassing
the modern business cycle theorists by simply turning the impish question
around and asking: "Expectations about what?" About changes in the overall
levels of prices and wages? About price and quantity changes in a one-commodity
world as perceived by a representative agent? About real and nominal changes
in the demand for back scratching? It should go without saying that a satisfactory
answer to the "Expectations about what?" question is a strict prerequisite
to a satisfactory answer to the "What about expectations?" question. And
for the Austrians, the prerequisite question is to be answered in terms
of the macroeconomics that predates its breaking away from the fundamentals.
In the Austrian view, the
issues of macroeconomics are inextricably bound up with the issues of microeconomics
and particularly with capital theory. The entrepreneurs, no one of whom
is representative of the economy as a whole, influence and are influenced
by one another as they bid for resources with which to carry out or possibly
to modify their production plans. Conflicting plans involving the provision
of immediately consumable services, such as Barro's back scratching, can
be quickly reconciled as potential consumers make decisions about whether
to purchase this service or to consume leisure and as they choose among
the alternative providers of it. If an economy could be usefully modeled
as the market for a single service provided by a representative supplier,
there would not likely be any issues that would give macroeconomics a distinct
subject matter. Important macroeconomic issues arise precisely to the extent
that the economics of back scratching is not the paradigm case,
which is to say, to the extent that inputs and outputs are not temporally
coincident. If resources must be committed well before the ultimate satisfaction
of consumer demand, then capital goods in some form must exist during the
period that spans the initial expectations of the entrepreneur and the
final choices of consumers. These capital goods can be conceived to include
human capital as well as capital in the more conventional sense and to
include durable capital goods as well as capital in the sense of goods
in process.
It is useful to think of
the production process as being divided into stages of production such
that the output of one stage is sold as input to a subsequent stage. Hayek
(1967) employed a simple right triangle to depicted the capital-using economy—which
gave him a leg up on Keynes, who paid no attention to production time.
This little piece of geometry will become an key element of our capital-based
macroeconomic model in Chapter 3. One leg of the triangle represents consumer
spending, the macroeconomic magnitude that had the attention of both Keynes
and Hayek; the other leg tracks the goods-in-process as the individual
plans of producers transform labor and other resources into the goods that
consumers buy. In Hayek's construction, human capital and durable capital
are ruled out for the sake of keeping the theory tractable and developing
a heuristic model, leaving us with the relatively simple conception of
capital as goods in process with a sequence of entrepreneurs having command
over these goods as they mature into consumable output. Still, there is
a nontrivial answer to the "Expectations about what?" question. Complicating
matters, however, is the fact that the sequence of stages is far from linear:
There are many feedback loops, multiple-purpose outputs, and other instances
of nonlinearities. Further, each stage may also involve the use of durable—but
depreciating—capital goods, relatively specific and relatively nonspecific
capital goods, and capital goods that are related with various degrees
of substitutability and complementarity to the capital goods in other stages
of production. These are the complications emphasized by Lachmann in his
Capital
and Its Structure.
It is this context in which
the Austrians can address the "Expectations about what?" question. The
proximate objects of entrepreneurial expectations relevant to a particular
stage of production include prices of inputs, which are the outputs of
earlier stages, and prices of outputs, which are inputs for subsequent
stages. The expected price differentials (between inputs and outputs) have
to be assessed in the light of current loan rates and of alternative uses
of existing capital goods. And judgments have to be made about possible
changes in credit conditions and in the market conditions for the eventual
consumer goods to which a particular stage of production contributes. Price,
wage, and interest-rate changes will have an effect on entrepreneurs' decisions,
and their decisions will have an effect on prices, wages, and interest
rates. This interdependency is what justifies the general conception of
the market as an economic process.
The market process facilitates
the translation of the underlying economic realities—resource availabilities,
technology, and consumer preferences (including intertemporal preferences)—into
production decisions guided by the expectations of the entrepreneurs. The
process plays itself out differently depending upon whether the interest
rate on which it is based is a faithful reflection of consumers' time preferences
or, owing to credit expansion by the central bank, a distortion of those
preferences. In the first case, the economy experiences sustainable growth;
in the second, it experiences boom and bust. This is the essence of the
Austrian theory of the business cycle (Mises et al., 1996; Garrison,
1986).
Two "assumptions" (a more
appropriate term here might be "understandings") about expectations are
implicit in the Austrian theory: (1) the entrepreneurs do not already know—and
cannot behave as if they already know—the underlying economic realities
whose changing characteristics are conveyed by changes in prices, wages,
and interest rates, and (2) prices, wages, and interest rates tend to facilitate
the coordination of economic decisions and to keep those decisions in line
with the underlying economic realities. Thinking broadly in terms of a
market solution to the economic problem, we see that a violation of the
first assumption implies a denial of the problem, while a violation of
the second assumption implies a denial that the market is a viable solution.
Taken together, these two assumptions do not allow us to categorize the
Austrians' treatment of expectations as static, adaptive, or rational,
as these terms have come to be used. But they do allow for a treatment
of expectations that is consistent with the view that there is an
economic problem and that the market is, at least potentially, a
viable solution to that problem. And dealing with expectations in the context
of a market process does give some basis for dealing with the Lachmann
problem identified early in this chapter. Expectations can be regarded
as largely endogenous—in a macroeconomically relevant sense—when the market
process has been set against itself and largely exogenous otherwise.
Consistency provides a standard
by which the alternative treatments of expectations can be compared. After
all, the idea of rational expectations stemmed from the recognition that
the assumptions of static expectations and even of adaptive expectations
were often inconsistent with the theories in which they were incorporated.
Lucas (1987, p. 13) refers to the rational expectation hypothesis as a
consistency axiom for economics. As such, the adjective "rational" refers
neither to a characteristic of the market participant whose expectations
are said to be rational nor to a quality of the expectations per se.
It refers to only to the relationship between the assumption about expectations
and the theory in which it is incorporated. The new classical assumption
of rational expectations may well be consistent with the monetary misperception
theory as set out in a Barro-style back-scratching model. But note that
both the assumption and the model are inconsistent with there being a significant
economic problem for which the market might provide a viable solution.
Accordingly, a rational-expectations assumption plucked from a new classical
formulation and inserted into Austrian theory—or into any other pre-Keynesian
theory that affirms the existence of an economic problem—would involve
an inconsistency, and hence, by the standard of consistency, would
no longer be "rational." That is, it is not logically consistent to claim
(1) that there is a representative agent who already has (or behaves as
if he already has) the information about the underlying economic realities
independent of current prices, wage rates and interest rates and
(2) that it is prices, wage rates and interest rates that convey this information.
The distinction between
local and global information together with the information lag that attaches
to global information allows for a telling point of comparison of new classical
and Austrian views. In the new classical construction, this knowledge problem
is contrived for the sake of modeling misperception. The representative
agent sees changes in money prices immediately but sees evidence of changes
in the money supply only belatedly. The agent does not know immediately,
then, whether the change in the money prices reflects a real change or
only a nominal change. In the Austrian theory, the treatment of the knowledge
problem rests upon a different distinction between two kinds of knowledge—a
distinction introduced by Hayek for the purpose of calling attention to
the nature of the economic problem broadly conceived. Hayek (1945) distinguishes
between the knowledge of the particular circumstances of time and place
and knowledge of the structure of the economy. Roughly, the distinction
is one between market savvy and theoretical understanding. It is not a
contrivance for the purposes of modeling misperception but rather an acknowledgment
of the fundamental insight most commonly associated with Adam Smith: The
market economy works without the market participants themselves having
to understand just how it works.
The strong version of rational
expectations employed by new classicism exhibits a certain symmetry with
the notion of rational planning conceived by advocates economic centralization.
The notions of both rational expectations and rational planning fail to
give adequate recognition to Hayek's distinction between the two kinds
of knowledge. Both employ the term "rational" to suggest, in effect, that
reasonable assumptions about one kind of knowledge can (rationally) be
extended to the other kind. Central planning could be an efficient means
of allocating resources if the planners, who, we will assume, have a good
theoretical understanding of the calculus of optimization, also had (or
behaved as if they had) the knowledge that is actually dispersed among
a multitude of entrepreneurs and other market participants. Symmetrically,
monetary policy would have no systematic effect on markets if entrepreneurs
and other market participants, whose knowledge of the particular circumstances
of time and place are mobilized by those markets, also had (or behaved
as if they had) a theoretical understanding of macroeconomic relationships.
To recognize Hayek's distinction and its significance is simply to acknowledge
that central planning is, in fact, not efficient and that monetary policy
can, in fact, have systematic effects.
Dealing with expectations
in the context of Hayek's distinction rather than in the context of the
contrived distinction between global and local knowledge adds a dimension
to Austrian economics that can be no part of new classicism. While the
global/local distinction is stipulated to separate two mutually exclusive
kinds of knowledge, the two kinds of knowledge identified by Hayek exhibit
an essential blending at the margin. Market participants must have some
understanding of how markets work, if only to know that lowering a price
is the appropriate response to a surplus and raising a price is the appropriate
response to a shortage. Suppliers of particular products as well as traders
in organized markets have a strong incentive to understand much more about
their respective markets—about current and expected changes in market conditions
and the implications for future prices. They know enough to make John Muth's
(1961) treatment of expectations as applied to the hog market seem not
only "rational" but eminently plausible. Symmetrically, economists-cum-policymakers
must have some knowledge about the particulars of the economy in order
to apply their theories to various existing circumstances. And to prescribe
policies aimed at a particular goal, such as a specific unemployment rate
or inflation rate, they would have to have a substantial amount of market
information—about how changes in actual market conditions affect, for instance,
the demand for labor and the demand for money.
Further, the extent of the
overlap is itself a matter of costs and benefits as experienced differentially
by policymakers and by market participants. For policymakers, additions
to their theoretical understanding are likely to be strongly complementary
to existing understandings and may even have synergistic effects, while
additional knowledge of the particular circumstances of time and place
would likely involve high costs and low benefits. A symmetrical statement
can be made about entrepreneurs with respect to costs and benefits of increased
market savvy as compared to increased theoretical understanding. In general,
specialists in one kind of knowledge experience sharply rising costs of—and
sharply declining benefits to—the other kind of knowledge. Putting the
matter in terms of costs and benefits suggests that the actual and/or perceived
costs and benefits can change. Undoubtedly, the extent to which policymakers
and market participants make use of both kinds of knowledge is dependent
on the institutional setting and the policy regime. Reform in the direction
of increased policy activism on the part of the central bank, for instance,
will increase the benefits to entrepreneurs and other market participants
of their understanding the short- and long-run relationships linking money
growth to interest rates, prices, and wages. Stated negatively, entrepreneurs
who experience a sequence of episodes in which the central bank is implementing
stabilization policy or attempting to "grow the economy" may face a high
cost of not understanding how money-supply decisions affect the
market process.
There is an overlap between
the two kinds of knowledge and the extent of the overlap is itself a result
of the market process. These aspects of Austrian theory have no counterpart
in new classical theory. Expectations will be based on the knowledge of
particular circumstances of time and place plus the understanding
that corresponds to the overlap. Expectations are not rational in the strong
sense of that term, but they do become more rational with increased levels
of policy activism and with cumulative experience with the consequences
of it. Equivalently stated, expectations are adaptive, but they adapt not
just to changes in some particular price, wage rate, or interest rate,
but also to the changing level of understanding that corresponds to the
overlap. Finally and significantly, further development of the issue of
expectations in the context of two kinds of knowledge and the market as
an economic process will involve an expansion rather than an implosion
of the Austrian research program.
What About Capital?
If we think in terms of market solutions to economic problems, we must
accord expectations a crucial role. But that role is overplayed if it is
assumed that expectations come ready made on the basis of information that
is actually revealed only as the market process unfolds; it is underplayed
if it is assumed that expectations are and forever remain at odds with
economic realities despite the unfolding of the market process. Either
assumption would detract from the equally crucial role played by the market
process itself, which alone can continuously inform expectations. On reflection,
we see that the near-obsessive focus on expectations in modern labor-based
macroeconomics owes much to the sterility of the theoretical constructions.
There is simply not much of anything else to focus upon.
What about capital? Much
of Austrian theory is aimed—either directly or indirectly—at providing
a satisfying answer to this question. And macroeconomists who think in
terms of a entrepreneurial decisions in the context of a complex intertemporal
capital structure have at the same time written much "about" expectations—even
if that very word does not appear in their every sentence. Ludwig Lachmann's
attention to expectations was always explicit as was his attention to capital
and its structure. Accordingly, we can credit him for setting an important
agenda for macroeconomics. Capital-based macroeconomics with due attention
to entrepreneurial expectations and the market process can compare favorably
with the modern labor-based macroeconomics and its assumption of rational
expectations.
|